極限思想外文翻譯pdf_第1頁
極限思想外文翻譯pdf_第2頁
極限思想外文翻譯pdf_第3頁
極限思想外文翻譯pdf_第4頁
極限思想外文翻譯pdf_第5頁
已閱讀5頁,還剩4頁未讀, 繼續(xù)免費(fèi)閱讀

下載本文檔

版權(quán)說明:本文檔由用戶提供并上傳,收益歸屬內(nèi)容提供方,若內(nèi)容存在侵權(quán),請(qǐng)進(jìn)行舉報(bào)或認(rèn)領(lǐng)

文檔簡(jiǎn)介

1、BSHM Bulletin, 2014Did Weierstrasss differential calculus have a limit-avoiding character? His definition of a limit in styleMICHIYO NAKANENihon University Research Institute of Science & Technology, JapanIn the 1820s, Cauchy founded his calculus on his original limit concept and developed his t

2、he-ory by using inequalities, but he did not apply these inequalities consistently to all parts of his theory. In contrast, Weierstrass consistently developed his 1861 lectures on differential calculus in terms of epsilonics. His lectures were not based on Cauchys limit and are distin-guished by the

3、ir limit-avoiding character. Dugacs partial publication of the 1861 lectures makes these differences clear. But in the unpublished portions of the lectures, Weierstrass actu-ally defined his limit in terms ofinequalities. Weierstrasss limit was a prototype of the modern limit but did not serve as a

4、foundation of his calculus theory. For this reason, he did not provide the basic structure for the modern e d style analysis. Thus it was Dinis 1878 text-book that introduced the definition of a limit in terms of inequalities.IntroductionAugustin Louis Cauchy and Karl Weierstrass were two of the mos

5、t important mathematicians associated with the formalization of analysis on the basis of the e d doctrine. In the 1820s, Cauchy was the first to give comprehensive statements of mathematical analysis that were based from the outset on a reasonably clear definition of the limit concept (Edwards 1979,

6、 310). He introduced various definitions and theories that involved his limit concept. His expressions were mainly verbal, but they could be understood in terms of inequalities: given an e, find n or d (Grabiner 1981, 7). As we show later, Cauchy actually paraphrased his limit concept in terms of e,

7、 d, and n0 inequalities, in his more complicated proofs. But it was Weierstrasss 1861 lectures which used the technique in all proofs and also in his defi-nition (Lutzen 2003, 185186).Weierstrasss adoption of full epsilonic arguments, however, did not mean that he attained a prototype of the modern

8、theory. Modern analysis theory is founded on limits defined in terms of e d inequalities. His lectures were not founded on Cauchys limit or his own original definition of limit (Dugac 1973). Therefore, in order to clarify the formation of the modern theory, it will be necessary to identify where the

9、 e d definition of limit was introduced and used as a foundation.We do not find the word limit in the published part of the 1861 lectures. Accord-ingly, Grattan-Guinness (1986, 228) characterizes Weierstrasss analysis as limit-avoid-ing. However, Weierstrass actually defined his limit in terms of ep

10、silonics in the unpublished portion of his lectures. His theory involved his limit concept, although the concept did not function as the foundation of his theory. Based on this discovery, this paper re-examines the formation of e d calculus theory, noting mathematicians treat-ments of their limits.

11、We restrict our attention to the process of defining continuity and derivatives. Nonetheless, this focus provides sufficient information for our purposes.First, we confirm that epsilonics arguments cannot represent Cauchys limit, though they can describe relationships that involved his limit concept

12、. Next, we examine how Weierstrass constructed a novel analysis theory which was not based2013 British Society for the History of Mathematics52BSHM Bulletinon Cauchys limits but could have involved Cauchys results. Then we confirm Weierstrasss definition of limit. Finally, we note that Dini organize

13、d his analysis textbook in 1878 based on analysis performed in the e d style.Cauchys limit and epsilonic argumentsCauchys series of textbooks on calculus, Cours danalyse (1821), Resume des lecons¸ donnees a lEcole royale polytechnique sur le calcul infinitesimal tome premier (1823), and Lecons&

14、#184; sur le calcul differentiel (1829), are often considered as the main referen-ces for modern analysis theory, the rigour of which is rooted more in the nineteenth than the twentieth century.At the beginning of his Cours danalyse, Cauchy defined the limit concept as fol-lows: When the successivel

15、y attributed values of the same variable indefinitely approach a fixed value, so that finally they differ from it by as little as desired, the last is called the limit of all the others (1821, 19; English translation from Grabiner 1981, 80). Starting from this concept, Cauchy developed a theory of c

16、ontinuous func-tions, infinite series, derivatives, and integrals, constructing an analysis based on lim-its (Grabiner 1981, 77).When discussing the evolution of the limit concept, Grabiner writes: This con-cept, translated into the algebra of inequalities, was exactly what Cauchy needed for his cal

17、culus (1981, 80). From the present-day point of view, Cauchy described rather than defined his kinetic concept of limits. According to his definitionwhich has the quality of a translation or descriptionhe could develop any aspect of the theory by reducing it to the algebra of inequalities.Next, Cauc

18、hy introduced infinitely small quantities into his theory. When the suc-cessive absolute values of a variable decrease indefinitely, in such a way as to become less than any given quantity, that variable becomes what is called an infinitesimal. Such a variable has zero for its limit (1821, 19; Engli

19、sh translation from Birkhoff and Merzbach 1973, 2). That is to say, in Cauchys framework the limit of variable x is c is intuitively understood as x indefinitely approaches c, and is represented as jx cj is as little as desired or jx cj is infinitesimal. Cauchys idea of defining infinitesimals as va

20、riables of a special kind was original, because Leibniz and Euler, for example, had treated them as constants (Boyer 1989, 575; Lutzen 2003, 164).In Cours danalyse Cauchy at first gave a verbal definition of a continuous func-tion. Then, he rewrote it in terms of infinitesimals:In other words, the f

21、unction f ðxÞ will remain continuous relative to x in a given interval if (in this interval) an infinitesimal increment in the variable always pro-duces an infinitesimal increment in the function itself. (1821, 43; English transla-tion from Birkhoff and Merzbach 1973, 2).He introduced the

22、infinitesimal-involving definition and adopted a modified version of it in Resume (1823, 1920) and Lecons¸ (1829, 278).Following Cauchys definition of infinitesimals, a continuous function can be defined as a function f ðxÞ in which the variable f ðx þ aÞ f ðxÞ

23、; is an infinitely small quantity (as previously defined) whenever the variable a is, that is, that f ðx þ aÞ f ðxÞ approaches to zero as a does, as noted by Edwards (1979, 311). Thus, the definition can be translated into the language of e d inequalities from a modern viewp

24、oint. Cauchys infinitesimals are variables, and we can also take such an interpretation.Volume 29 (2014)53Cauchy himself translated his limit concept in terms of e d inequalities. He changed If the difference f ðx þ 1Þ f ðxÞ converges towards a certain limit k, for increasin

25、g values of x, (. . .) to First suppose that the quantity k has a finite value, and denote by e a number as small as we wish. . . . we can give the number h a value large enough that, when x is equal to or greater than h, the difference in question is always contained between the limits k e; k þ

26、; e (1821, 54; English translation from Bradley and Sandifer 2009, 35).In Resume, Cauchy gave a definition of a derivative: if f ðxÞ is continuous, then its derivative is the limit of the difference quotient,as i tends to 0 (1823, 2223). He also translated the concept of derivative as foll

27、ows: Designate by d and e two very small numbers; the first being chosen in such a way that, for numerical values of i less than d, . . ., the ratio f ðx þ iÞ f ðxÞ=i always remains greater than f ðx Þ e and less than f ðxÞ þ e (1823, 4445; English t

28、ransla-tion from Grabiner 1981, 115).These examples show that Cauchy noted that relationships involving limits or infinitesimals could be rewritten in term of inequalities. Cauchys arguments about infinite series in Cours danalyse, which dealt with the relationship between increasing numbers and inf

29、initesimals, had such a character. Laugwitz (1987, 264; 1999, 58) and Lutzen (2003, 167) have noted Cauchys strict use of the e N characterization of convergence in several of his proofs. Borovick and Katz (2012) indicate that there is room to question whether or not our representation using e d ine

30、qualities conveys messages different from Cauchys original intention. But this paper accepts the inter-pretations of Edwards, Laugwitz, and Lutzen.Cauchys lectures mainly discussed properties of series and functions in the limit process, which were represented as relationships between his limits or

31、his infinitesi-mals, or between increasing numbers and infinitesimals. His contemporaries presum-ably recognized the possibility of developing analysis theory in terms of only e, d, and n0 inequalities. With a few notable exceptions, all of Cauchys lectures could be rewrit-ten in terms of e d inequa

32、lities. Cauchys limits and his infinitesimals were not func-tional relationships,1 so they were not representable in terms of e d inequalities.Cauchys limit concept was the foundation of his theory. Thus, Weierstrasss full epsilonic analysis theory has a different foundation from that of Cauchy.Weie

33、rstrasss 1861 lecturesWeierstrasss consistent use of e d argumentsWeierstrass delivered his lectures On the differential calculus at the Gewerbe Insti-tut Berlin2 in the summer semester of 1861. Notes of these lectures were taken by1Edwards (1979, 310), Laugwitz (1987, 260261, 271272), and Fisher (1

34、978, 16318) point out that Cauchys infinitesimals equate to a dependent variable function or aðhÞ that approaches zero as h ! 0. Cauchy adopted the latter infinitesimals, which can be written in terms of e d arguments, when he intro-duced a concept of degree of infinitesimals (1823, 250; 1

35、829, 325). Every infinitesimal of Cauchys is a vari-able in the parts that the present paper discusses.2A forerunner of the Technische Universitat Berlin.54BSHM BulletinHerman Amandus Schwarz, and some of them have been published in the original German by Dugac (1973). Noting the new aspects related

36、 to foundational concepts in analysis, full e d definitions of limit and continuous function, a new definition of derivative, and a modern definition of infinitesimals, Dugac considered that the nov-elty of Weierstrasss lectures was incontestable (1978, 372, 1976, 67).3After beginning his lectures b

37、y defining a variable magnitude, Weierstrass gave the definition of a function using the notion of correspondence. This brought him to the following important definition, which did not directly appear in Cauchys theory:(D1) If it is now possible to determine for h a bound d such that for all values

38、of h which in their absolute value are smaller than d, f ðx þ hÞ f ðxÞ becomes smaller than any magnitude e, however small, then one says that infinitely small changes of the argument correspond to infinitely small changes of the function. (Dugac 1973, 119; English translati

39、on from Calinger 1995, 607)That is, Weierstrass defined not infinitely small changes of variables but infinitely small changes of the arguments correspond(ing) to infinitely small changes of function that were presented in terms of e d inequalities. He founded his theory on this correspondence.Using

40、 this concept, he defined a continuous function as follows:(D2) If now a function is such that to infinitely small changes of the argument there correspond infinitely small changes of the function, one then says that it is a continuous function of the argument, or that it changes continuously with t

41、his argument. (Dugac 1973, 119120; English translation from Calinger 1995, 607)So we see that in accordance with his definition of correspondence, Weierstrass actually defined a continuous function on an interval in terms of epsilonics. Since (D2) is derived by merely changing Cauchys term produce t

42、o correspond, it seems that Weierstrass took the idea of this definition from Cauchy. However, Weierstrasss definition was given in terms of epsilonics, while Cauchys definition can only be interpreted in these terms. Furthermore, Weierstrass achieved it without Cauchys limit.Luzten (2003, 186) indi

43、cates that Weierstrass still used the concept of infinitely small in his lectures. Until giving his definition of derivative, Weierstrass actually continued to use the term infinitesimally small and often wrote of a function which becomes infinitely small with h. But several instances of infinitesim

44、ally small appeared in forms of the relationships involving them. Definition (D1) gives the rela-tionship in terms of e d inequalities. We may therefore assume that Weierstrasss lectures consistently used e d inequalities, even though his definitions were not directly written in terms of these inequ

45、alities.Weierstrass inserted sentences confirming that the relationships involving the term infinitely small were defined in terms of e d inequalities as follows:(D3) If h denotes a magnitude which can assume infinitely small values, ðhÞ is an arbitrary function of h with the property that

46、 for an infinitely small value of h it3The present paper also quotes Kurt Bings translation included in Calingers Classics of mathematics.Volume 29 (2014)55also becomes infinitely small (that is, that always, as soon as a definite arbitrary small magnitude e is chosen, a magnitude d can be determine

47、d such that for all values of h whose absolute value is smaller than d, ðhÞ becomes smaller than e). (Dugac 1973, 120; English translation from Calinger, 1995, 607)As Dugac (1973, 65) indicates, some modern textbooks describe ðhÞ as infinitely small or infinitesimal.Weierstrass a

48、rgued that the whole change of function can in general be decom-posed asDf ðxÞ ¼ f ðx þ hÞ f ðxÞ ¼ p:h þ hðhÞð1Þwhere the factor p is independent of h and ðh Þ is a magnitude that becomes infinitely small with h.4 Howeve

49、r, he overlooked that such decomposition is not possible for all functions and inserted the term in general. He rewrote h as dx. One can make the difference between Df ðxÞ and p:dx smaller than any magnitude with decreasing dx. Hence Weierstrass defined differential as the change which a f

50、unction undergoes when its argument changes by an infinitesimally small magnitude and denoted it as df ðxÞ. Then, df ðxÞ ¼ p:dx. Weierstrass pointed out that the differential coefficient p is a function of x derived from f ðxÞ and called it a derivative (Dugac 1973

51、, 120121; English translation from Calinger 1995, 607608). In accordance with Weierstrasss definitions (D1) and (D3), he largely defined a derivative in terms of epsilonics.Weierstrass did not adopt the term infinitely small but directly used e d inequalities when he discussed properties of infinite series involving uniform conver-gence (Dugac 1973, 122124)

溫馨提示

  • 1. 本站所有資源如無特殊說明,都需要本地電腦安裝OFFICE2007和PDF閱讀器。圖紙軟件為CAD,CAXA,PROE,UG,SolidWorks等.壓縮文件請(qǐng)下載最新的WinRAR軟件解壓。
  • 2. 本站的文檔不包含任何第三方提供的附件圖紙等,如果需要附件,請(qǐng)聯(lián)系上傳者。文件的所有權(quán)益歸上傳用戶所有。
  • 3. 本站RAR壓縮包中若帶圖紙,網(wǎng)頁內(nèi)容里面會(huì)有圖紙預(yù)覽,若沒有圖紙預(yù)覽就沒有圖紙。
  • 4. 未經(jīng)權(quán)益所有人同意不得將文件中的內(nèi)容挪作商業(yè)或盈利用途。
  • 5. 人人文庫網(wǎng)僅提供信息存儲(chǔ)空間,僅對(duì)用戶上傳內(nèi)容的表現(xiàn)方式做保護(hù)處理,對(duì)用戶上傳分享的文檔內(nèi)容本身不做任何修改或編輯,并不能對(duì)任何下載內(nèi)容負(fù)責(zé)。
  • 6. 下載文件中如有侵權(quán)或不適當(dāng)內(nèi)容,請(qǐng)與我們聯(lián)系,我們立即糾正。
  • 7. 本站不保證下載資源的準(zhǔn)確性、安全性和完整性, 同時(shí)也不承擔(dān)用戶因使用這些下載資源對(duì)自己和他人造成任何形式的傷害或損失。

評(píng)論

0/150

提交評(píng)論