版權(quán)說明:本文檔由用戶提供并上傳,收益歸屬內(nèi)容提供方,若內(nèi)容存在侵權(quán),請進行舉報或認領(lǐng)
文檔簡介
1、PAGE 31/31PAGE 31 This is a course about justice and we begin with a story。 Suppose youre the driver of a trolley car, and your trolley car is hurtling down the track at 60 miles an hour. And at the end of the track, you notice five workers working on the track。 You try to stop but you cant, your br
2、akes dont work。 You feel desperate because you know that if you crash into these five workers, they will all die。 Lets assume you know that for sure。 And so you feel helpless until you notice that there is, off to the right, a side track and at the end of that track, there is one worker working on t
3、he track. Your steering wheel works, so you can turn the trolley car, if you want to, onto the side track killing the one but sparing the five。 Heres our first question: whats the right thing to do? What would you do? Lets take a poll。 How many would turn the trolley car onto the side track? Raise y
4、our hands。 How many wouldnt? How many would go straight ahead? Keep your hands up those of you who would go straight ahead. A handful of people would, the vast majority would turn。 Lets hear first, now we need to begin to investigate the reasons why you think its the right thing to do. Lets begin wi
5、th those in the majority who would turn to go onto the side track. Why would you do it? What would be your reason? Whos willing to volunteer a reason? Go ahead。 Stand up。 Because it cant be right to kill five people when you can only kill one person instead. It wouldnt be right to kill five if you c
6、ould kill one person instead. Thats a good reason。 Who else? Does everybody agree with that reason? Go ahead. Well I was thinking its the same reason on 9/11 with regard to the people who flew the plane into the Pennsylvania field as heroes because they chose to kill the people on the plane and not
7、kill more people in big buildings. So the principle there was the same on 9/11. Its a tragic circumstance but better to kill one so that five can live, is that the reason most of you had, those of you who would turn? Yes? Lets hear now from those in the minority, those who wouldnt turn。 Yes。 Well, I
8、 think thats the same type of mentality that justifies genocide and totalitarianism. In order to save one type of race, you wipe out the other。 So what would you do in this case? You would, to avoid the horrors of genocide, you would crash into the five and kill them? Presumably, yes. You would?-Yea
9、h。 Okay。 Who else? Thats a brave answer. Thank you。 Lets consider another trolley car case and see whether those of you in the majority want to adhere to the principle: ”better that one should die so that five should live.” This time youre not the driver of the trolley car, youre an onlooker。 Youre
10、standing on a bridge overlooking a trolley car track. And down the track comes a trolley car, at the end of the track are five workers, the brakes dont work, the trolley car is about to careen into the five and kill them。 And now, youre not the driver, you really feel helpless until you notice stand
11、ing next to you, leaning over the bridge is a very fat man. And you could give him a shove。 He would fall over the bridge onto the track right in the way of the trolley car。 He would die but he would spare the five。 Now, how many would push the fat man over the bridge? Raise your hand。How many would
12、nt? Most people wouldnt。 Heres the obvious question。 What became of the principle better to save five lives even if it means sacrificing one?” What became of the principlethat almost everyone endorsed in the first case? I need to hear from someone who was in the majority in both cases。 How do you ex
13、plain the difference between the two? Yes。 The second one, I guess, involves an active choice of pushing a person downwhich I guess that person himself would otherwise not have been involved in the situation at all。 And so to choose on his behalf, I guess, to involve him in something that he otherwi
14、se would have escaped is, I guess, more than what you have in the first case where the three parties, the driver and the two sets of workers, are already, I guess, in the situation. But the guy working, the one on the track off to the side, he didnt choose to sacrifice his life any more than the fat
15、 man did, did he? Thats true, but he was on the tracks and.。 This guy was on the bridge.Go ahead, you can come back if you want。 All right。 Its a hard question。 You did well. You did very well。 Its a hard question.Who else can find a way of reconciling the reaction of the majority in these two cases
16、? Yes。 Well, I guess in the first case where you have the one worker and the five, its a choice between those two and you have to make a certain choice and people are going to die because of the trolley car, not necessarily because of your direct actions. The trolley car is a runaway thingand youre
17、making a split second choice. Whereas pushing the fat man over is an actual act of murder on your part。 You have control over that whereas you may not have control over the trolley car。 So I think its a slightly different situation. All right, who has a reply? Thats good. Who has a way? Who wants to
18、 reply? Is that a way out of this? I dont think thats a very good reason because you choose to either way you have to choose who dies because you either choose to turn and kill the person, which is an act of conscious thought to turn, or you choose to push the fat man over which is also an active, c
19、onscious action。 So either way, youre making a choice。 Do you want to reply? Im not really sure that thats the case。 It just still seems kind of different. The act of actually pushing someone over onto the tracks and killing him, you are actually killing him yourself。 Youre pushing him with your own
20、 hands.Youre pushing him and thats different than steering something that is going to cause death into another. You know, it doesnt really sound right saying it now. No, no。 Its good。 Its good.Whats your name? Andrew。 Andrew. Let me ask you this question, Andrew。 Yes. Suppose standing on the bridge
21、next to the fat man, I didnt have to push him, suppose he was standing over a trap door that I could open by turning a steering wheel like that。 Would you turn? For some reason, that still just seems more wrong。 Right? I mean, maybe if you accidentally like leaned into the steering wheel or somethin
22、g like that。 But。 Or say that the car is hurtling towards a switch that will drop the trap。 Then I could agree with that。 Thats all right. Fair enough。 It still seems wrong in a way that it doesnt seem wrong in the first case to turn, you say. And in another way, I mean, in the first situation youre
23、 involved directly with the situation。 In the second one, youre an onlooker as well。 All right. So you have the choice of becoming involved or not by pushing the fat man。 All right. Lets forget for the moment about this case.Thats good。 Lets imagine a different case. This time youre a doctor in an e
24、mergency room and six patients come to you。 Theyve been in a terrible trolley car wreck。Five of them sustain moderate injuries,one is severely injured, you could spend all day caring for the one severely injured victim but in that time, the five would die. Or you could look after the five, restore t
25、hem to health but during that time, the one severely injured person would die。 How many would save the five? Now as the doctor, how many would save the one? Very few people, just a handful of people. Same reason, I assume。One life versus five? Now consider another doctor case. This time, youre a tra
26、nsplant surgeon and you have five patients, each in desperate need of an organ transplant in order to survive。One needs a heart, one a lung, one a kidney,one a liver, and the fifth a pancreas。And you have no organ donors.You are about to see them die。And then it occurs to you that in the next room t
27、heres a healthy guy who came in for a check-up. And hes you like that and hes taking a nap, you could go in very quietly,yank out the five organs, that person would die, but you could save the five。 How many would do it?Anyone? How many? Put your hands up if you would do it.Anyone in the balcony? I
28、would.You would? Be careful,dont lean over too much. How many wouldnt? All right. What do you say? Speak up in the balcony, you who would yank out the organs。 Why? Id actually like to explore a slightly alternate possibility of just taking the one of the five who needs an organ who dies first and us
29、ing their four healthy organs to save the other four。 Thats a pretty good idea。 Thats a great idea except for the fact that you just wrecked the philosophical point。 Lets step back from these stories and these arguments to notice a couple of things about the way the arguments have begun to unfold. C
30、ertain moral principles have already begun to emerge from the discussions weve had。 And lets consider what those moral principles look like. The first moral principle that emerged in the discussion said the right thing to do, the moral thing to do depends on the consequences that will result from yo
31、ur action。 At the end of the day, better that five should live even if one must die. Thats an example of consequentialist moral reasoning。 Consequentialist moral reasoning locates morality in the consequences of an act, in the state of the world that will result from the thing you do。 But then we we
32、nt a little further, we considered those other cases and people werent so sure about consequentialist moral reasoning。 When people hesitated to push the fat man over the bridge or to yank out the organs of the innocent patient, people gestured toward reasons having to do with the intrinsic quality o
33、f the act itself, consequences be what they may. People were reluctant. People thought it was just wrong, categorically wrong, to kill a person, an innocent person, even for the sake of saving five lives。 At least people thought that in the second version of each story we considered. So this points
34、to a second categorical way of thinking about moral reasoning.Categorical moral reasoning locates morality in certain absolute moral requirements, certain categorical duties and rights, regardless of the consequences. Were going to explore in the days and weeks to come the contrast between consequen
35、tialist and categorical moral principles. The most influential example of consequential moral reasoning is utilitarianism, a doctrine invented by Jeremy Bentham, the 18th century English political philosopher. The most important philosopher of categorical moral reasoning is the 18th century German p
36、hilosopher Immanuel Kant. So we will look at those two different modes of moral reasoning, assess them, and also consider others。 If you look at the syllabus, youll notice that we read a number of great and famous books, books by Aristotle, John Locke, Immanuel Kant, John Stewart Mill, and others。 Y
37、oull notice too from the syllabus sthat we dont only read these books; we also take up contemporary, political, and legal controversies that raise philosophical questions. We will debate equality and inequality, affirmative action, free speech versus hate speech, same sex marriage, military conscrip
38、tion, a range of practical questions。 Why? Not just to enliven these abstract and distant books but to make clear, to bring out whats at stake in our everyday lives, including our political lives, for philosophy. And so we will read these books and we will debate these issues, and well see how each
39、informs and illuminates the other. This may sound appealing enough, but here I have to issue a warning。 And the warning is this,to read these books in this way as an exercise in self knowledge, to read them in this way carries certain risks, risks that are both personal and political, risks that eve
40、ry student of political philosophy has known。 These risks spring from the fact that philosophy teaches us and unsettles usby confronting us with what we already know。 Theres an irony。 The difficulty of this course consists in the fact that it teaches what you already know. It works by taking what we
41、 know from familiar unquestioned settings and making it strange. Thats how those examples worked, the hypotheticals with which we began, with their mix of playfulness and sobriety。 Its also how these philosophical books work。 Philosophy estranges us from the familiar, not by supplying new informatio
42、n but by inviting and provoking a new way of seeing but, and heres the risk, once the familiar turns strange, its never quite the same again。 Self knowledge is like lost innocence, however unsettling you find it; it can never be un-thought or unknown。 What makes this enterprise difficult but also ri
43、veting is that moral and political philosophy is a story and you dont know where the story will lead. But what you do know is that the story is about you. Those are the personal risks。 Now what of the political risks? One way of introducing a course like this would be to promise you that by reading
44、these books and debating these issues, you will become a better, more responsible citizen; you will examine the presuppositions of public policy, you will hone your political judgment, you will become a more effective participant in public affairs。 But this would be a partial and misleading promise。
45、 Political philosophy, for the most part, hasnt worked that way. You have to allow for the possibility that political philosophy may make you a worse citizen rather than a better one or at least a worse citizen before it makes you a better one, and thats because philosophy is a distancing, even debi
46、litating, activity. And you see this, going back to Socrates, theres a dialogue, the Gorgias, in which one of Socrates friends, Callicles, tries to talk him out of Philosophizing. Callicles tells Socrates Philosophy is a pretty toy if one indulges in it with moderation at the right time of life。 But
47、 if one pursues it further than one should, it is absolute ruin.” ”Take my advice,” Callicles says, ”abandon argument。 Learn the accomplishments of active life, take for your models not those people who spend their time on these petty quibbles but those who have a good livelihood and reputation and
48、many other blessings?!?So Callicles is really saying to Socrates ”Quit philosophizing, get real, go to business school?!?And Callicles did have a point。 He had a point because philosophy distances us from conventions, from established assumptions, and from settled beliefs. Those are the risks, perso
49、nal and political. And in the face of these risks, there is a characteristic evasion. The name of the evasion is skepticism, its the idea well, it goes something like this we didnt resolve once and for all either the cases or the principles we were arguing when we began and if Aristotle and Locke an
50、d Kant and Mill havent solved these questions after all of these years, who are we to think that we, here in Sanders Theatre, over the course of a semester, can resolve them? And so, maybe its just a matter of each person having his or her own principles and theres nothing more to be said about it,
51、no way of reasoning. Thats the evasion, the evasion of skepticism, to which I would offer the following reply。 Its true, these questions have been debated for a very long time but the very fact that they have recurred and persisted may suggest that though theyre impossible in one sense, theyre unavo
52、idable in another. And the reason theyre unavoidable, the reason theyre inescapable is that we live some answer to these questions every day. So skepticism, just throwing up your hands and giving up on moral reflection is no solution。 Immanuel Kant described very well the problem with skepticism whe
53、n he wrote Skepticism is a resting place for human reason, where it can reflect upon its dogmatic wanderings, but it is no dwelling place for permanent settlement.” ”Simply to acquiesce in skepticism,” Kant wrote, can never suffice to overcome the restlessness of reason?!?Ive tried to suggest throug
54、h these stories and these arguments some sense of the risks and temptations, of the perils and the possibilities。 I would simply conclude by saying that the aim of this course is to awaken the restlessness of reason and to see where it might lead。 Thank you very much. Like, in a situation that despe
55、rate, you have to do what you have to do to survive。 You have to do what you have to do? You got to do what you got to do, pretty much. If youve been going 19 days without any food, you know, someone just has to take the sacrifice。 Someone has to make the sacrifice and people can survive。 Alright, t
56、hats good。 Whats your name? Marcus。 -Marcus, what do you say to Marcus? Last time, we started out last time with some stories, with some moral dilemmas about trolley cars and about doctors and healthy patients vulnerable to being victims of organ transplantation。 We noticed two things about the argu
57、ments we had, one had to do with the way we were arguing. We began with our judgments in particular cases。 We tried to articulate the reasons or the principles lying behind our judgments. And then confronted with a new case, we found ourselves reexamining those principles, revising each in the light
58、 of the other。 And we noticed the built in pressure to try to bring into alignment our judgments about particular cases and the principles we would endorse on reflection。 We also noticed something about the substance of the arguments that emerged from the discussion。 We noticed that sometimes we wer
59、e tempted to locate the morality of an act in the consequences, in the results, in the state of the world that it brought about。 And we called this consequentialist moral reasoning. But we also noticed that in some cases, we werent swayed only by the result。 Sometimes, many of us felt, that not just
60、 consequences but also the intrinsic quality or character of the act matters morally。 Some people argued that there are certain thing that are just categorically wrong even if they bring about a good result, even if they saved five people at the cost of one life。 So we contrasted consequentialist mo
溫馨提示
- 1. 本站所有資源如無特殊說明,都需要本地電腦安裝OFFICE2007和PDF閱讀器。圖紙軟件為CAD,CAXA,PROE,UG,SolidWorks等.壓縮文件請下載最新的WinRAR軟件解壓。
- 2. 本站的文檔不包含任何第三方提供的附件圖紙等,如果需要附件,請聯(lián)系上傳者。文件的所有權(quán)益歸上傳用戶所有。
- 3. 本站RAR壓縮包中若帶圖紙,網(wǎng)頁內(nèi)容里面會有圖紙預(yù)覽,若沒有圖紙預(yù)覽就沒有圖紙。
- 4. 未經(jīng)權(quán)益所有人同意不得將文件中的內(nèi)容挪作商業(yè)或盈利用途。
- 5. 人人文庫網(wǎng)僅提供信息存儲空間,僅對用戶上傳內(nèi)容的表現(xiàn)方式做保護處理,對用戶上傳分享的文檔內(nèi)容本身不做任何修改或編輯,并不能對任何下載內(nèi)容負責(zé)。
- 6. 下載文件中如有侵權(quán)或不適當(dāng)內(nèi)容,請與我們聯(lián)系,我們立即糾正。
- 7. 本站不保證下載資源的準確性、安全性和完整性, 同時也不承擔(dān)用戶因使用這些下載資源對自己和他人造成任何形式的傷害或損失。
最新文檔
- 小說藝術(shù)特色課程設(shè)計
- 《智慧旅游視域下我國滑雪旅游創(chuàng)新發(fā)展研究》
- 《我國房地產(chǎn)行業(yè)稅收制度研究》
- 《史料實證視域下文言文史料教學(xué)的應(yīng)用研究》
- 餐飲行業(yè)促銷與價格調(diào)整方案
- 電影《八佰》觀后心得體會
- 2024-2030年中國汽車用鋼行業(yè)供給預(yù)測及發(fā)展規(guī)劃分析報告
- 2024-2030年中國汽車標準件行業(yè)競爭趨勢及發(fā)展策略分析報告
- 2024-2030年中國汽車安全氣囊行業(yè)市場發(fā)展需求及投資戰(zhàn)略分析報告
- 2024-2030年中國汽車內(nèi)飾粘合劑項目申請報告
- 肺結(jié)核病防治知識宣傳培訓(xùn)
- 圓錐曲線中定點和定值問題的解題方法市公開課一等獎省賽課微課金獎?wù)n件
- 2024年4月自考00015英語(二)試題
- DB11/T 691-2009-市政工程混凝土模塊砌體構(gòu)筑物結(jié)構(gòu)設(shè)計規(guī)程
- 高三一模作文“文學(xué)不是我生命中的唯一”導(dǎo)寫
- (2024年)功能醫(yī)學(xué)與健康管理
- 合理膳食健康教育知識講座課件
- 2024年內(nèi)蒙古大興安嶺農(nóng)墾集團有限責(zé)任公司招聘筆試參考題庫附帶答案詳解
- 中國傳統(tǒng)文化知識競賽試題題庫(附答案)
- 寧德時代2024年社招測評題庫
- 安全生產(chǎn)投入臺賬(模板)
評論
0/150
提交評論