![此為英文文檔nber -Corporate Social Responsibility and Voting over Public Goods_第1頁(yè)](http://file4.renrendoc.com/view/3a3988358d666b794470cbed956d6c23/3a3988358d666b794470cbed956d6c231.gif)
![此為英文文檔nber -Corporate Social Responsibility and Voting over Public Goods_第2頁(yè)](http://file4.renrendoc.com/view/3a3988358d666b794470cbed956d6c23/3a3988358d666b794470cbed956d6c232.gif)
![此為英文文檔nber -Corporate Social Responsibility and Voting over Public Goods_第3頁(yè)](http://file4.renrendoc.com/view/3a3988358d666b794470cbed956d6c23/3a3988358d666b794470cbed956d6c233.gif)
![此為英文文檔nber -Corporate Social Responsibility and Voting over Public Goods_第4頁(yè)](http://file4.renrendoc.com/view/3a3988358d666b794470cbed956d6c23/3a3988358d666b794470cbed956d6c234.gif)
![此為英文文檔nber -Corporate Social Responsibility and Voting over Public Goods_第5頁(yè)](http://file4.renrendoc.com/view/3a3988358d666b794470cbed956d6c23/3a3988358d666b794470cbed956d6c235.gif)
版權(quán)說(shuō)明:本文檔由用戶提供并上傳,收益歸屬內(nèi)容提供方,若內(nèi)容存在侵權(quán),請(qǐng)進(jìn)行舉報(bào)或認(rèn)領(lǐng)
文檔簡(jiǎn)介
NBERWORKINGPAPERSERIES
CORPORATESOCIALRESPONSIBILITYANDVOTINGOVERPUBLICGOODS
AndrewA.Samwick
SophieWang
WorkingPaper31633
/papers/w31633
NATIONALBUREAUOFECONOMICRESEARCH
1050MassachusettsAvenue
Cambridge,MA02138
August2023
WethankthePresidentialScholarsfundatDartmouthforfinancialsupportandRajeshAggarwal,JulianLamprecht,NafisaLohawala,ErzoLuttmer,XuejuanSu,CurtWelling,seminarparticipantsattheWEAI98thAnnualConferenceandtheIIPF79thAnnualCongress,OmraneGuedhami(theeditor)andananonymousrefereeforusefulcomments.Anyerrorsareourown.TheviewsexpressedhereinarethoseoftheauthorsanddonotnecessarilyreflecttheviewsoftheNationalBureauofEconomicResearch.
NBERworkingpapersarecirculatedfordiscussionandcommentpurposes.Theyhavenotbeenpeer-reviewedorbeensubjecttothereviewbytheNBERBoardofDirectorsthataccompaniesofficialNBERpublications.
?2023byAndrewA.SamwickandSophieWang.Allrightsreserved.Shortsectionsoftext,nottoexceedtwoparagraphs,maybequotedwithoutexplicitpermissionprovidedthatfullcredit,including?notice,isgiventothesource.
CorporateSocialResponsibilityandVotingoverPublicGoods
AndrewA.SamwickandSophieWang
NBERWorkingPaperNo.31633
August2023
JELNo.D72,H41,M14
ABSTRACT
Thispaperanalyzestheimpactofcorporatesocialresponsibility(CSR)onthetotalprovisionofpublicgoodsinaframeworkinwhichconsumerswhomaymakesuchvoluntarycontributionstopublicgoodsviaCSRarealsovoterswhodecideontheleveloftaxestofinancepubliclyprovidedpublicgoods.Themainresultindicatesthat,relativetoaneconomyinwhichallpublicgoodsarepubliclyfinanced,theintroductionofCSRlowersthetotalamountofpublicgoods,asvotersrationallyanticipatethathigherCSRwillpartiallyoffsettheconsequencesoflowerpublicfunding.TheresultsofferacautionarytaleaboutthepromotionofCSRinaneconomywithheterogeneouspreferencesforthepublicgood.
AndrewA.Samwick
6106RockefellerHall
DepartmentofEconomics
DartmouthCollege
Hanover,NH03755-3514
andNBER
andrew.samwick@
SophieWang
DartmouthCollege
sophie.wang32@
1
1Introduction
TheBusinessRoundtablemadeheadlinesin2019when,forthe?rsttimeinovertwodecades,itissueda
StatementonthePurposeofaCorporation
thatacknowledgedspeci?cresponsibilitiestostakeholdersbeyondshareholders,includingcustomers,em-ployees,suppliers,andcommunities.SuchCorporateSocialResponsibility(CSR)hasbeengrowingmarkedlyinrecentyears.
Dattanietal.
(2015)establishabaselineof
$20billionspentonCSRin2013byGlobalFortune500companies.
Stobierski
(2021)
reportsthatbetween2011and2019,theshareofS&P500companiespublishingaCSRReportrosefrom20to90percent.
InareviewoftheearlyeconomicsliteratureonCSR,
KitzmuellerandShimshack
(2012)de?neCSRas“thecorporateprovisionofpublicgoodsorreductionofnegative
externalitiesbeyondwhatisrequiredbylaw.”MuchofthescholarlydiscussionofCSRhasfocusedonthemotivesthatshareholderswouldhaveforCSR,startingwithandoftenrespondingto
Friedman
(1970)’sseminalessay.
Hisconclusionthattheonlysocialresponsibilityofbusinessistoincreasepro?tsisfacilitatedbyassumptionsthatshareholderscanachievetheirphilanthropicobjectivesequallywelloutsidethe?rmandwouldprefertodoso.
Forexample,underlyingFriedman’scontentionistheassumptionthattherearenoadvantagestocontributionsbyshareholdersactinginconcertviathecorporationrelativetocontributingasindividualsontheirown.Contrarytothisassumption,
B′enabouandTirole
(2010)positthatthe?rmmayfacelowertransactionscostsin
makingdonationsormitigatingexternalitiesasarationaleforshareholdersdelegatingphilanthropythroughCSR.
1
Inabriefessaycommemoratingthe50thanniversaryof
Friedman
(1970),
Hart
(2020)expandsthisargumentbynotingthatgivingthrough
thecorporationmayhelpovercomefree-riderproblemsinindividualgivingtopub-licgoods,aseachshareholder’s“donation”isconditionalonthedonationsofalltheothershareholders.Additionally,asseveralauthors,mostnotably
Baron
(2001),have
noted,CSRmaybe“strategic”inthesensethatitrespondstostakeholderprefer-encesforthisvoluntaryovercomplianceand,indoingso,mayenhancepro?tability.
2
1ElGhouletal.
(2017)showthatCSRismorepositivelyassociatedwith?rmvalue(asmea
-suredbyTobin’sq)incountrieswithweakermarketinstitutions,suggestingthatCSRishelpingtocounteractgreatertransactioncostsandlimitedaccesstoresources.
2Thatcompaniesarerespondingtostakeholderpreferencesissuggestedby
Rubin
(2008)’s?ndings
thatcompanieswithhighCSRratingsaretypicallyin“blue”statesorcountieswhereascompanieswithlowCSRratingsaretypicallyin“red”statesorcounties.Similarly,
DiGiuliandKostovetsky
2
Friedmanacknowledgedthispossibilityinhisessayandfocusedinsteadonvalue-reducingCSRthatrespondstomanagerialpreferencesthatdi?erfromthoseoftheshareholders.
However,CSRcanalsoemergeastheexpresseddesireofshareholdersratherthanasanagencycon?ictbetweenshareholdersandmanagers.As
HartandZingales
(2017)argue,shareholdersoftenactinprosocialways,attheirownexpense,intheir
isolateddecisionsasindividuals.Itisnaturalthattheywouldalsoseektodosointheirrolesasshareholders,whentheycansharethecostsoftheirphilanthropicbehaviorwithothers.Inlightofthis,maximizingshareholderwelfareneednotbethesameasmaximizingmarketvalue.Further,
Baron
(2007)developsatheoryof
CSRinananalyticalmodelthatre?ectstheeconomicenvironmentenvisionedby
Friedman
(1970)andshowsthatprosocialentrepreneurswillform?rms,evenata
?nancialloss,toopenupnewopportunitiesforotherstoengageinCSR
.3
LesswelldevelopedintheexistingliteraturearethedownstreamconsequencesoftheavailabilityofCSRonthebehaviorofthestakeholdersotherthanshareholders.Toanalyzesuchconsequences,weabstractfromtheshareholderconsiderationsnotedabove,assumeidenticalcostsforthepublicgoodacrossprivateCSRandtax-?nancedpublicprovision,andpositfreeentryby?rmsthatdriveseconomicpro?tstozeroforanydegreeofCSR.
4
Ourmodeltakesasitsstartingpointthatof
BesleyandGhatak
(2007),whoshowthatastylizedversionofCSRcanbemodeledintheframework
ofvoluntary,privatecontributionstopublicgoodsintroducedby
Bergstrometal.
(1986)
.Inamodelofpurepublicgoodswithtwotypesofconsumers–thosewhocareaboutthepublicgoodandthosewhodonot–theydemonstratethatCSRgeneratesaParetoimprovement,ascaringconsumerswillengageinCSRandneutralconsumerswillnotchangetheirbehavior.Theyfurthershowthatanexogenous
(2014)?ndthat?rmswithDemocraticfoundersorCEOsspendmoreonCSR.Whiletheyalso?nd
thatincreasesin?rmCSRratingsareassociatedwithnegativefuturestockreturnsanddeclinesinthe?rm’sreturnonassets,
Friedeetal.
(2015)?nd,inaggregatingdatafromover2,000studies,that
thereisgenerallyanonnegative(thoughnotnecessarilycausal)relationshipbetweenenvironmental,social,andgovernancecriteriaandcorporate?nancialperformance.
3See
SchmitzandSchrader
(2015)foramoreextensivediscussionofthemotivescorporations
mighthaveforCSR.Inarecentsurveyoftheliterature,
HongandShore
(2022)concludethat
shareholderinterestinCSRisdrivenprimarilybynon-pecuniarymotives–awillingnesstosacri?cereturnstoaddressvarious?rmexternalities–ratherthanbypecuniarymotiveslikethepursuitofabnormalratesofreturn.
4WethusalsoabstractfromtheinteractionofCSRwitholigopolisticcompetition.See
Bagnoli
andWatts
(2003)forsuchamodel
.
increaseinthepublicprovisionofthepublicgoodwillcrowdoutvoluntaryprovisionbyCSR.
OurinvestigationofCSRismotivatedbytheobservationthattheconsumerswhodecidewhethertoengageinCSRviatheirpurchasesarealsothevoterswhodecidewhethertotaxthemselvestoprovidethepublicgoodthroughthepublicsector.Toconsidertheimplicationsofthisduality,weaugmentthemodelof
Besleyand
Ghatak
(2007)intwoways.First,weallowformultiplecaringtypesofconsumers,
whoengageinCSRtovaryingdegreesaccordingtotheirpreferences.Thischangetothemodelnecessitatesusingtheversionoftheirmodelwithanimpurepublicgood,incorporatingthe“warmglow”ofgivingdescribedby
Andreoni
(1989,
1990).
5
Inourmodel,individualsdi?eronlyintheintensityoftheirpreferenceforthepublicgood,withseparateparametersindexingthedirectutilityfromthetotalstockofpublicgoodsandthewarmglowofgivingthroughCSR.Second,weintroducea?rst-stageofvotingontheamountoftax-?nancedpublicgoodtobeprovided.The“warmglow”isassumedtobegeneratedbythevoluntarycontributionstopublicgoodsprovidedthroughCSRbutnotbytaxes.
EndogenizingtheamountofthepublicgoodprovidedthroughtaxesallowsustoconsidertheextenttowhichtheprospectofsubsequentCSRbyconsumerscrowdsoutpublicprovisionbyvoters.Wecomparethelevelofpublicgoodsunderthreeregimesdistinguishedbyhowtheycanbefunded:PublicOnlythroughtaxes,VoluntaryOnlythroughCSR,andPublicandVoluntarythroughboth.WederivetheequilibriumundereachregimeandshowthatthetotalprovisionofpublicgoodsislowerwhenCSRandpublicprovisionarebothpossiblecomparedtowhenallpublicgoodsareprovidedpubliclythroughtaxes.VotersrationallyanticipatethatlowerCSRwillpartiallyo?settheconsequencesofhigherpublicfunding,andthiso?setlowersthemarginalbene?tofsupportinghighertaxesto?nancepublicprovision.Foragivenmarginalcostofprovidingthepublicgood,thisreductioninthemarginalbene?treducestheequilibriumamountofthepublicgood.Ingeneral,theadditionofCSRopportunitiesdoesnotgenerateaParetoimprovement.Weshowconditionsunderwhichamajoritycoalitionprefersthehybridregime,despiteitslowerlevelofpublicgoods.
Ourresultsaremostsimilartothepriorworkof
Calverasetal.
(2011)and
Epple
5SeeCornesandSandler(1994)foranearlyanalysisofthecomparativestaticpropertiesofsuch
amodel.
3
4
andRomano
(2003),whoexploreprivatecontributionstopublicgoodsinframeworks
withoutexplicitCSR.
Calverasetal.
(2011)de?neamore“altruistic”societyasone
inwhichwarmglowpreferencesforprivatecontributionsarestronger.Theyshowthatmajorityvotinginamorealtruisticsocietyleadstoalowertaxrateandmayalsoleadtolowerequilibriumprovisionofthepublicgood.
EppleandRomano
(2003)
useaframeworkinwhichhouseholdshavethesamepreferencesbutdi?erintheirendowmentsofincome.Householdsvoteoveranincometaxbutdonotfacealabor-leisuretradeo?.Theyshowthatwhilepermittingprivatecontributionsmayleadtoareductionintotalprovisionofthepublicgood,amajorityalwaysfavorspermittingprivatecontributions.
Theremainderofthepaperisorganizedasfollows.InSection
2
,weexpandtheframeworkof
BesleyandGhatak
(2007)toincorporatemultiplecaringtypes
withawarmglowofCSR.Westartwiththesocialoptimumandthenderivetheequilibriumlevelsofpublicgoodswhenthereisa?rststageofmajorityvotingbeforeCSRdecisionstakeplace.WecomparepublicgoodprovisionunderthethreeregimesinSection
3
,derivingthemainresultthatCSRreducesthetotalamountofpublicgoods.WeprovideconditionsforamajoritytopreferthehybridregimeinSection
4
andconsidertheimpactofchangesinpreferencestowardmorecaringforpublicgoodsinSection
5
.Section
6
discussestheimplicationsofour?ndingsandconcludes.Theresultso?eracautionarytaleaboutallowingandpromotingCSRiftheobjectiveistoincreasethetotalamountofthepublicgood.
2Model
Ourmodelbuildsonthatof
BesleyandGhatak
(2007),whoanalyzeCSRinthe
contextofamodelwithtwotypesofconsumers,caringandneutraltowardCSR.Weadopttheirnotationwherepossible.Becauseweseektostudytheinterplaybe-tweenvotingforpubliclyprovidedpublicgoodsandCSR,weexpandtheirframeworktohavemultipletypesthatmightcare,todi?erentextents,aboutthepublicgood,throughboththetotalamountofthepublicgoodandthe“warmglow”thatcon-sumersgetthroughtheirindividualamountsofCSR.Individualsdecide,asvoters,onanamountofthepublicgoodprovidedbythepublicsectorwhilethesameindi-viduals,asconsumers,decideonhowmuchCSRtoengageinviatheirconsumption.Inbothcases,ourassumptionsaremeanttobelessrestrictiveandmorerealistic,
5
acknowledgingthatvotersareultimatelyresponsibleforsettingtheleveloftaxesandthuspubliclyprovidedpublicgoodsandthatpreferencesforpublicgoodsaremorevariedthanapopulationthateithercaresornotaboutthelevelofpublicgoods.
Themodelof
BesleyandGhatak
(2007)issetinanenvironmentwherethereis
onetypeofpublicgoodandtwotypesofprivategoods.Thepublicgoodmustbeproducedwhileoneprivategoodisproducedandtheotherisendowedtoallproducersandconsumersintheamountb.ConsumerscanmakevoluntarycontributionstothepublicgoodthroughCSRbybuyingfromaproducerthatbundlestheprivategoodwithanamountθofthepublicgood.Eachunitofthepublicgoodcostsα,whetherproducedbythepublicsectorinamountGorcontributedviaCSR.TheyalsoassumethereisfreeentryfromproducerswhocompeteinBertrandfashionandthusearnzeropro?ts.Theyproducetheprivategoodatcostcplusαθ,fortheamountoftheCSRassociatedwiththepurchase.Withzeropro?ts,thepricefortheprivategoodbundledwithanamountθofthepublicgoodisp=c+αθ.Themodelthusabstractsfrombothentrepreneurs’motivationsforCSRandanyinteractionofCSRwithstrategiccompetitioninproductmarkets.
WeassumeapopulationofindividualsofsizeNwhoaredistinguishedbytheirpreferenceparametersforthepublicgood,γiandηi.Wespecifyautilityfunctionforindividualioftheform:
Ui=b.(c+αθi).+γif(G+Θ)+ηiv(θi)(1)
Publicgoodsprovidedbythepublicsectorare?nancedbyalumpsumtax,in?rstisthroughthetotalamountofthepublicgood,G+Θ,whereΘ=!θi.Thefunctionf(G+Θ)isassumedtobeincreasingandstrictlyconcave,withf(>0andf((<0.ThesecondisthroughthewarmglowoftheCSR,v(θi),similarlywithv(>0andv((<0.
6
Ourapproachistoimposeminimalassumptionsonthejointdistributionofthepreferenceparameters,{γi,ηi},beyondtheirnon-negativityandatechnicalassumptionthatifγiisnon-zero,thenηiisalsonon-zero.Thus,ourmodeldi?ersfrom
BesleyandGhatak
(2007)inthreemainways.First,weallowfor
anon-exogenouslevelofGwhichis?nancedbyalumpsumtax.Second,weallow
6Theseassumptionsareconsistentwiththe?ndingsof
Carpenter
(2021),whousesa?eldexper
-imenttoshowthatfordonorsmotivatedbythewarmglowofgiving,itsshapeisincreasingandconcave.
6
formultipletypesbeyondγ=0orγ=1.Third,theexistenceofmultipletypesengaginginCSRrequirestheassumptionof“warmglow”utility,which,as
Besley
andGhatak
(2007)note,leavestheirmainresultsessentiallyunchanged.Insodoing,
weintroduceaseparatepreferenceparametertoindexthestrengthofthewarmglow,asdistinctfromthestrengthofthepreferenceforthetotalamountofthepublicgood.
2.1ASocialPlanner’sProblem
Beforederivingequilibriaindecentralizedmodels,weconsiderasocialplannerwhomaximizesaggregatewelfare,basedonEquation(
1
):
W=[b.(c+αθi).+γif(G+Θ)+ηiv(θi)](2)
Wenotethatindividualsdi?eronlywithrespecttotheparameters,γiandηi,andnotwithrespecttotheirendowment,b.Thus,thereisnoredistributivemotiveforthetaxbasedonunequalendowmentsandnoparticularreasontoweightdi?erentindividuals’utilitiesdi?erently.Thelumpsumtaxisakintoamembershipfeeinagroupofindividualswhodi?eronlyintheirpreferenceparameters.
SummingovertheNconsumers,wecanwrite:
W=N(b.c).α(G+Θ)+(γi)f(G+Θ)+(ηiv(θi))(3)
ThesocialplannerwouldchooseGand{θ1,...,θN}tomaximizethisexpression,subjecttotheconstraintsthatGc0andθic0,Ⅴi.IntheabsenceofCSR,thesocialplannerwouldchooseGaccordingtothe?rst-ordercondition:
α=(γi)f((FB)(4)
Equation(
4
)isthefamiliaroptimalityconditionthatthemarginalcostofthepublicgoodshouldequalthesumofthemarginalutilitiesofthegoodacrossallconsumers.
7
Herewemaketheimplicitassumptionthatthemarginalutilityatzero
publicgoodsissu?cientlyhigh,f((0)>,sothatFB>0.WithCSRavailable
atthesameresourcecostaspublicprovision,however,itisclearfromEquation(
3
)
7WedenotethischoiceofGasFB,withthetildeindicatingthatthisisnotavaluechosen
simultaneouslywiththevaluesof{θ1!!!!!θN}whenCSRisavailable.
7
thatasocialplannerwouldsetG=0giventheassumptionthatv(>0.AnypositiveamountofGcouldbereallocatedtosomeindividual’sθi,generatingawarmglowandthusanincreaseinaggregatewelfare,whilekeepingthetotalcostofthepublicgood,.α(G+Θ),andthedirectutilityfromthetotalamountofthepublicgood,f(G+Θ),unchanged.
WithGFB=0,thesocialplannerwouldchooseeachvalueofθjaccordingtothe?rst-ordercondition:
α=!γi(f((ΘFB)+ηjv((θ)(5)
Inthiscase,themarginalcostofproducingthepublicgoodmustbeequaltothesumofthemarginalutilitiesofthepublicgoodacrossallconsumersplusthemarginalutilityofthewarmglowforindividualj.Theassumptionthatv((<0ensuresthat
θisincreasinginηjamongthoseengaginginCSR.Comparingthetwo?rst-order
conditions,wecanseethatbecausev(>0,f((ΘFB)<f((FB),andthatbecause
f((<0,itmustbethatΘFB>FB.Thus,undertheseconditions,thepresence
ofCSRwithawarmglowincreasesthesociallyoptimalamountofthepublicgoodprovided.
Inthis?rst-bestallocation,wecande?nethesetofcontributors,CFB,asthepairsof{(γi,ηi)}suchthattheright-handsideofthe?rst-orderconditioninEquation(
5
)withθ=0exceedstheleft-handside:
CFB={(γi,ηi)|α<γif((ΘFB)+ηiv((0)}(6)
The?rst-bestwillbesuchthatallindividualswith(γi,ηi)∈CFBwillengageinCSRasgivenbyEquation(
5
)andthosewith(γi,ηi)CFBwillnotengageinCSR
.8
2.2VotingasaFirstStage
Wenextconsiderhowequilibriumamountsofthepublicgoodaredeterminedinadecentralizedmodelwithtwostages.Inthe?rststage,individualsvoteontheamount
8Inhisanalysisoftheoptimaltaxtreatmentofprivatecontributionsforpublicgoods,
Diamond
(2006)discussescircumstancesunderwhichitwouldnotbeappropriatetoincludethewarmglowin
thesocialplanner’sobjectivefunction.Inthiscase,thetotalamountofG+ΘisgivenbyEquation
(4),butthedistributionofthatamountacrosspublicandprivatecontributionsisnotdetermined
.
8
ofthepublicgood,G
.9
Inthesecondstage,individualsmaketheirconsumptiondecisionsoverhowmuchCSRtoengagewiththeirprivategoodpurchase,θi,atanadditionalcostofαθi.Whenindividualsvoteinthe?rststage,theyanticipatehowtheamountofthepublicgoodprovidedthroughtaxeswilla?ecttheCSRchoicesofallpotentialconsumersinthesecondstage.
ReturningtotheindividualutilityfunctioninEquation(
1
),andtemporarilysuppressingtheisubscriptsforreadability,wecanconsidertheconsumer’schoiceinthesecondstagebyholdingG?xedin:
b.(c+αθ).+γf(G+Θ)+ηv(θ)(7)
ForagivenamountofG,eachindividual(inthesecondstage)willmaximizethisutilitywithrespecttoθ,yieldingthe?rst-ordercondition:
γf((G+Θ)+ηv((θ)=α(8)
Thisequationimplicitlyde?nesarelationshipbetweenthechoicesofθandthevalueofG
.10
Asabove,thesetofcontributors,C,includesallcombinationsof{γ,η}suchthat:
C={(γ,η)|α<γf((G+Θ)+ηv((0)}(9)
Forsuchconsumers,themarginalbene?toftheadditionalCSR,throughboththedirectutilityofthepublicgoodandthewarmglow,isgreaterthantheresourcecostofproducingit.Fortheseconsumerswith(γ,η)∈C,the?rst-orderconditioninEquation(
8
)determinestheirchoiceofθ.
Movingbacktothe?rststage,takingthederivativeofEquation(
7
)withrespecttoGyieldsthe?rst-orderconditionforavotercontemplatingwhethertosupportan
increaseinG:
9Individualsinthemodelarenotmakingalabor-leisuretradeo?,andincomeisequalacrossindividuals,soanincometaxisidenticaltoauniformlumpsumtaxasmodeledhere.
10Equation(
8
)showswhythewarmglowassumptionisnecessaryinthismodelinwhichmorethanonecaringconsumerengagesinCSR.Withf()thesameacrossconsumers,absentthev≥()term,therewouldbenowayforthis?rst-orderconditiontoholdsimultaneouslyfortwodi?erentvaluesof.Similarly,thisisthereasonforthetechnicalassumptionthatmustbepositiveforanyconsumerwithpositive.
9
.α.+γf((G+Θ)╱1++ηv((θ)=0(10)
whichcanberewrittenas:
=γf((G+Θ)╱1++(ηv((θ).α)(11)
IfthisvoterengagesinCSR,withθ>0,thensubstitutinginthe?rst-orderconditionforθf(wàn)romEquation(
8
)intothelastterminEquation(
11
)yields:
=γf((G+Θ)╱1+.(12)
IfinsteadthevoterdoesnotengageinCSR,withθ=0,then=0,andEquation(
11
)reducesto:
=γf((G+Θ)╱1+(13)
Inbothequations,theleft-handsideistheindividualvoter’smarginalcostofanadditionalunitofG,andtheright-handsideisthevoter’smarginalbene?tofthatadditionalunit.The?rst-orderconditionincorporatesthepossibledependenceofeachθ,andthereforeΘ,onG.Inbothequations,themarginalbene?tofthepublicgood?nancedthroughthelumpsumtaxisequaltotherelativeweightonthepublicgoodintheutilityfunction,γ,multipliedbythemarginalutilityofanadditionalunitofthepublicgood,f((G+Θ),multipliedbythenete?ectoftheincreaseinGon
thetotalstockofthepublicgood,╱1+..Aswewilldiscussbelow,because
f((<0,thetotalamountofthepublicgood,G+Θ,ispositivelyrelatedtothisnete?ect.
Toobtainananalyticalexpressionforthisnete?ect,wetakethetotalderivativeofthe?rst-orderconditionforθinEquation(
8
):
γf(((G+Θ)>dG+γf(((G+Θ)>dΘ+ηv(((θ)>dθ=0
Dividingthroughbyγf(((G+Θ)>dGyields:
1++>>=0
dΘηv(((θ)dθ
dGγf(((G+Θ)dG
(14)
(15)
10
Equation(
15
)showsthatwithv()andf()strictlyconcave,crowdingoutwillbe
imperfect,1+>0,aslongascrowdoutexistsforsomeindividual,
<0.(Note
thatcrowdingoutwouldbeperfectforv((=0.)Thisexpressionfor1+canbesubstitutedintoEquation(
12
)toobtain:
=.γf((G+Θ)(1+>
(16)
Thelaststepisto?ndananalyticalexpressionfor.Reintroducingsubscriptsiandjtodistinguishdi?erentindividuals,Equation(
15
)impliesthat:
(17)
>>=>>
foranyijsuchthatθi,θj>0.Thus,
Byde?nition,
dθidG
=ΣiEC
=
>>
dG
>dθj
(18)
wherethesummationonlyappliestothesubsetof
consumerswhoengageinCSR.Nowthatwehaveanexpressionforintermsof,wecansubstitutethisintoEquation(
15
)andrearrangetoget
1+(>>+>=0
andsubstitutingbackintoEquation(
16
)gives:
α
N
=γjf((G+Θ)
(1+>
(ΣiEC>>+
Factoringout>,givesa?nalexpression:
α((1+>
N=γjf(G+Θ)(1+ΣiEC>
(19)
(20)
(21)
Whenthisvoterdoesnotengageitcanbeshownthatthenewexpressionforthisvoter’schoiceofGis:
11
11Thestepsinthederivationarethesame,recognizingthatthe1inthenumeratorinEquation
(20)isnotpresentbecausethevoterisnotengaginginCSR.
11
αN
=γjf((G+Θ)
1
╱1+!iEC>
(22)
IfvoterpreferencesforGaresingle-peaked,thenthemedianvotertheoremwillapply,andwecanexpressEquations(
21
)and(
22
)as:
αN
=γmedf((G+Θ)Kmed
(23)
Here,Kmedisthe?naltermineitherofthetwopriorequationswithjchosentobethevoterwiththemedianvalueofγj.AsinEquations(
12
)and(
13
),itcorrespondstothenete?ectofanincreaseinGontheamountofCSRcontributedbyconsumersotherthanthemedianvoter.Kmedispositivebecausef()andv()arestrictlyincreasingandconcave.ItislessthanonebecausethedenominatorislargerthanthenumeratoraslongasatleastoneconsumerengagesinCSR
.12
Thus,publicprovisionofthepublicgoodimperfectlycrowdsoutvoluntarypro-visionthroughCSR.Thedegreeofcrowdingoutdependsontherelativemagnitudesof|f((|and|v((|.Kmedislower,andthuscrowdingoutishigher,when|f((|ishighrelativeto|v((|.Insuchcases,agivenchangeinGgeneratesalargeo?settingchangeinθithrougheachconsumer’s?rst-ordercondition.
Equation(
23
),combinedwiththe?rst-orderconditioninEquation(
8
)foreachconsumerwhoengagesinCSRo
溫馨提示
- 1. 本站所有資源如無(wú)特殊說(shuō)明,都需要本地電腦安裝OFFICE2007和PDF閱讀器。圖紙軟件為CAD,CAXA,PROE,UG,SolidWorks等.壓縮文件請(qǐng)下載最新的WinRAR軟件解壓。
- 2. 本站的文檔不包含任何第三方提供的附件圖紙等,如果需要附件,請(qǐng)聯(lián)系上傳者。文件的所有權(quán)益歸上傳用戶所有。
- 3. 本站RAR壓縮包中若帶圖紙,網(wǎng)頁(yè)內(nèi)容里面會(huì)有圖紙預(yù)覽,若沒(méi)有圖紙預(yù)覽就沒(méi)有圖紙。
- 4. 未經(jīng)權(quán)益所有人同意不得將文件中的內(nèi)容挪作商業(yè)或盈利用途。
- 5. 人人文庫(kù)網(wǎng)僅提供信息存儲(chǔ)空間,僅對(duì)用戶上傳內(nèi)容的表現(xiàn)方式做保護(hù)處理,對(duì)用戶上傳分享的文檔內(nèi)容本身不做任何修改或編輯,并不能對(duì)任何下載內(nèi)容負(fù)責(zé)。
- 6. 下載文件中如有侵權(quán)或不適當(dāng)內(nèi)容,請(qǐng)與我們聯(lián)系,我們立即糾正。
- 7. 本站不保證下載資源的準(zhǔn)確性、安全性和完整性, 同時(shí)也不承擔(dān)用戶因使用這些下載資源對(duì)自己和他人造成任何形式的傷害或損失。
最新文檔
- 木工班合同(二次結(jié)構(gòu))
- 2025年度辦事處裝修與辦公家具采購(gòu)及維護(hù)服務(wù)合同
- 2025年度辦公室文件消毒與消毒劑研發(fā)與品牌合作合同
- 2025年度安全生產(chǎn)應(yīng)急處理與事故處理服務(wù)合同
- 報(bào)社陽(yáng)臺(tái)照明設(shè)備節(jié)能改造合同2025
- 2025年也門(mén)文版辦公室租賃合同(含品牌形象推廣)
- 藝術(shù)館花園整修合同樣本
- 消防二次改造施工合同
- 三農(nóng)村醫(yī)療衛(wèi)生服務(wù)規(guī)范指南
- 三農(nóng)田管理最佳實(shí)踐方案與指南
- 數(shù) 學(xué)2024-2025學(xué)年人教版七年級(jí)數(shù)學(xué)上冊(cè)有理數(shù)混合運(yùn)算100題
- 2024年銀行考試-農(nóng)村信用社考試近5年真題附答案
- 人教版小學(xué)數(shù)學(xué)四年級(jí)下冊(cè)第一單元測(cè)試卷附答案(共9套)
- 二年級(jí)上冊(cè)100以內(nèi)加減法豎式計(jì)算題200道及答案
- 新滬科版八年級(jí)物理第三章光的世界各個(gè)章節(jié)測(cè)試試題(含答案)
- 人教版五年級(jí)上冊(cè)四則混合運(yùn)算300道及答案
- 非遺國(guó)粹川劇變臉的傳統(tǒng)文化知識(shí)了解原創(chuàng)模板
- 統(tǒng)編版六年級(jí)下冊(cè)道德與法治1-學(xué)會(huì)尊重-課件(54張課件)
- 5.5.1三角恒等變換(第一課時(shí))課件高一上學(xué)期數(shù)學(xué)人教A版
- 中國(guó)智慧物流發(fā)展報(bào)告
- 導(dǎo)演聘用合同正式(2024版)
評(píng)論
0/150
提交評(píng)論